[This note has been compiled copying contents from the
articles written by Hamza Andreas tzortzis]
“Science is the only way or method to render truths about
the world and reality”- this assertion is known as scientism. To put it simply,
scientism claims that a statement is not true if it cannot be scientifically
proven. In other words if something cannot be shown to be true via the
scientific method, then it is false. There are a few problems with scientism,
for instance:
1. Scientism is self-defeating. Scientism claims that a
proposition is not true if it cannot be scientifically proven. However, the
above claim itself cannot be scientifically proven. Therefore, according to
this claim, the claim itself is not true, hence scientism self-defeating.
2. Scientism cannot prove necessary truths like mathematics
and logic. For example, "3 + 3 = 6" is necessary truth and not merely
empirical generalisation. In fact, scientism requires these necessary truths,
but it cannot prove them, and any attempt to do so would be tantamount to
arguing in a circle.
3. Scientism cannot prove moral and aesthetic truths. For
example love, beauty, right and wrong.
To explain the false assertion of scientism we would
like to discuss the following points here:
1. Science
does not claim certainty or 100% truth.
2. There are
other ways to render truths about the world and reality.
1. Science does not claim certainty or 100% truth
Science is commonly thought to just involve a method or a
set of steps that one has to take to ensure the results of an experiment or
theory are scientific. While this is true, the philosophy of science – which is
the way in which we reach conclusions from the results of a particular
experiment – is often a neglected topic of popular science and rarely discussed
in the public domain.
So what is the scientific method and the philosophy of
science?
The scientific method
The word science comes from the Latin word scientia, meaning
knowledge. A concise definition of science has been accurately stated by the
philosopher Bertrand Russell,
The attempt to discover, by means of observation and
reasoning based upon it, … particular facts about the world, and the laws
connecting facts with one another.[1]
Philosophy of science
The philosophy of science focuses on deriving and building
knowledge from the evidence gathered from testing a testable idea. For that
reason, it concerns itself with the implications of the data collected from an
experiment, the metaphysical assumptions used to interpret the data, and the
thinking processes used to form conclusions based on scientific evidence.
The philosophy of
science is a field of study that attempts to address how we can derive
knowledge from scientific experiments and empirical data. Key problems in the
philosophy of science include induction and empiricism, as they
both have limitations and a restricted scope. Understanding these issues will
enable us to reach the conclusion that scientific facts are not 100% and there
is always the possibility of doubt.
a)
Induction:
Induction is a thinking process
where one makes conclusions by moving from the particular to the general.
Arguments based on induction can range in probability from very low to very
high, but always less than 100%. Here is an example of induction:
“I have observed that punching a
boxing bag properly with protective gloves never causes injury. Therefore no
one will be injured using a boxing bag.”
As can be seen from the example
above, induction faces a key problem which is the inability to guarantee the
conclusion, because a sweeping generalisation cannot be made from a limited
number of observations. The best it can provide are probabilities, ranging from
low to very high. In the aforementioned example the person who made the
statement could not logically prove that the next person to punch a boxing bag
will not get injured.
Therefore, the problem with
induction is that it can’t produce certainty. This issue was raised by the 18th
century Scottish philosopher David Hume in his book, An Enquiry Concerning
Human Understanding. Hume argued that inductive reasoning can never produce
certainty. He concluded that moving from a limited set of observed phenomena to
making conclusions for an unlimited set of observed phenomena is beyond the
present testimony of the senses, and the records of our memory. [2]
From a practical scientific
perspective, generalisations made for an entire group or for the next
observation within that group, based on a limited set of data will never be
certain. Take the following example into consideration, a scientist travelled
to Wales and wanted to find out the colour of sheep (assuming he does not know
the colour of sheep). He started observing the sheep and recorded what colour
they were. After 150 sheep observations he found that all of them were white.
The scientist concluded, using induction, that all sheep are white. This basic
example highlights the problematic nature with the process of induction as we
know sheep can also be black. Certainty using induction will never be achieved,
because there is always the possibility of new observations undermining the
previous conclusion.
b)
Empiricism:
Empiricism claims that we have no
source of knowledge in a subject or for the concepts we use in a subject other
than sense experience. Philosopher Elliot Sober in his essay Empiricism
explains the empiricist’s thesis:
“Empiricists deny that it is ever
rationally obligatory to believe that theories provide true descriptions of an unobservable
reality…For an empiricist, if a theory is logically consistent, observations
are the only source of information about whether the theory is empirically
adequate.”[3]
Empiricism suffers from
limitations and logical problems. The main problem with empiricism is that it
can only base its conclusions on observed realities and cannot make conclusions
on unobserved realities. Elliot Sober explains this problem:
“Empiricists need to address
problems in the philosophy of perception. The most obvious first stab at saying
what seeing an object involves is to describe the passage of light from the
object into the eyes, with the result that a visual experience occurs. However,
the invisibility of white cats in snowstorms and the fact that we see silhouettes
(like the moon during an eclipse) shows that this is neither sufficient nor
necessary.”[4]
Further exploring Sober’s
example, imagine you observe a white cat walking outside of a house towards the
direction of an oncoming snowstorm; you can see the cat walking up to the
snowstorm and then you can no longer see the cat. A strong empiricist’s account
would be to deny that there is a cat in the snowstorm, or at least suspend any
claims to knowledge. However, based on other intellectual tools at your disposal
you would conclude that there is a white cat in the snowstorm regardless of
whether or not you can observe one.
In light of the above, since
induction and empiricism are used in deriving knowledge from scientific data
then science cannot claim certainty. There are the obvious problems of the
unobserved and the inability to guarantee that the next observation will be the
same as the previous observation. Our observations do not encompass all
phenomena, therefore science is tentative. In other words it can change based
upon future observations. For science to be certain, all natural phenomena must
have been observed. This is impossible.
2. There are other ways to render truths about the world and reality.
A major problem with scientism is that truths can be
established outside the scientific paradigm. For example, ”Authentic Testimony”
and “Divine Revelation”.
Authentic Testimony
Authentic testimony is a valid source of knowledge in which
epistemologists have argued at length to explain that the say-so of others can
– within certain criteria – provide a basis for truth.
The epistemology of testimony is the branch of the theory of
knowledge “concerned with how we acquire knowledge and justified belief from
the say-so of other people“.[5] Therefore, one of the key questions it tries to
answer is “how we successfully acquire justified belief or knowledge on the
basis of what other people tell us.“[6]
Many truths that we hold are on the basis of authentic
testimony, because we trust the statements of others and we have no good reason
to reject what they have said. This is especially so when we have multiple
people telling us the same thing via different chains of transmission (known as
tawattur reporting in Islamic thought). Professor C. A. J. Coady highlights some
of the truths we accept on the basis of testimony, he writes,
“Many of us have never seen a baby born, nor have most of us
examined the circulation of the blood…”[7]
Assistant Professor
Benjamin McMyler in his book Testimony, Truth and Authority, explains that some
of the things he knows are due to testimony,
“Here are a few things that I know. I know that the
copperhead is the most common venomous snake in the greater Houston area. I
know that Napoleon lost the Battle of Waterloo. I know that, as I write, the
average price for gasoline in the U.S is $4.10 per gallon. And I know that my
parents recently returned home from a trip to Canada. All of these things I
know on the basis of what epistemologists call testimony, on the basis of being
told of them by another person or group of persons.”[8]
Although this is a vast topic, there is a general consensus
that authentic testimony is a source of knowledge. However, there are
disagreements amongst epistemologists on how we validate the transmission of
knowledge via testimony. Even scientists require testimony as a source of
knowledge in order to understand science itself. For instance, there are many
assumptions in science that are purely based on the say so of other scientists.
Whatever discussions there are around testimony, the key
point to raise here is that it is a valid source of knowledge. Therefore, the
view that science is the only way to establish truth is false. Professor Keith
Lehrer summarises the validity of testimony as a source of knowledge,
“The final question that arises concerning our acceptance of
testimony is this. What converts our acceptance of testimony of others into
knowledge? The first part of the answer is that we must be trustworthy in our
evaluations of the trustworthiness of others, and we must accept that this is
so. Moreover, our trustworthiness must be successfully truth-connected, that
is, the others must, in fact, be trustworthy and their trustworthiness must be
truth-connected. We must accept this is so. In short, our acceptance of their
testimony must be justified in a way that is not refuted or defeated by any
errors that we make in evaluating them and their testimony. Undefeated or
irrefutable justified acceptance of the testimony of others is knowledge.”[9]
Although scientism – as an issue in the philosophy of
science – does not seem to provide problems for evolution, it is useful to
highlight that non-scientific sources of knowledge may also play a vital role
in our understanding of who we are and where we came from. It logically follows
that since science is not the only way to reach conclusions about things, then
we should entertain the possibility of other routes to knowledge.
Divine Revelation
Divine revelation is certain knowledge (this type of certain
knowledge is known as al-‘ilm al-qat’i)
which can be proven using deductive arguments.
If Divine revelation is from God, then by definition its
knowledge claims are true or certain. There is the obvious caveat that this
depends on our understanding of what the revelation says and if we have come to
the correct interpretation, however, the point here is that since it comes from
the Divine – who is the All-Knowing and transcends our limitations – then what
the revelation says is going to be true. An important point to highlight is
that there are some unequivocal verses in the Quran and some that are open to
interpretation. It seems contradictory to make this claim about the Qur’an when
some of its verses will be uncertain from the perspective of what they imply
and mean. However, interpreting the Qur’an has been made an intellectual
endeavour between suitably qualified exegetes. What we are saying here is that
the proposition here concerns the ontology of knowledge – its source and
nature. Therefore, if the Qur’an is from the Divine it follows that its
knowledge claims are true, regardless if we understand what these claims to
knowledge are, because by definition God is the All-Knowing and His knowledge
transcends human knowledge.
The article does not intend to present a detailed case for
how the Qur’an is from God; however it is important to note that using methods
outside of the scientific paradigm, it can be rationalised that the book cannot
have come from a human being. In other words there are no naturalistic
explanations to explain the authorship of the Qur’an. There are various
arguments to justify the above claim. For instance, Muslims can rely on
deductive arguments to explain the miraculous nature of the Qur’an. Deductive
arguments are arguments which the premises guarantee the truth of the
conclusion. If the premises of a deductive argument are true then it is
impossible for the conclusion to be false.
Here are some examples of deductive arguments:
1. Whatever begins to exist has a cause
2. The universe began to exist
3. Therefore the universe has a cause
1. All men are mortal.
2. George is a man.
3. Therefore, George is mortal.
The above are examples of valid and sound arguments. A deductive argument is valid if the
conclusion follows from its premises. It is sound if its premises are true and
it is valid. With regards to the Qur’an there are many deductive arguments that
can substantiate its claim of being a Divine book. For example, there is a well-known
deductive argument concerning the literary miracle of the Qur’an,
1. A miracle is an event that lies outside of the productive
capacity of nature (there are no causal links between the event and the nature
of the event).
2. The Qur’an’s literary form lies outside of the productive
capacity of nature (its literary form cannot be logically explained using the
Arabic language).
3. Therefore, the Qur’an is a miracle (a miracle is an act
of God).
This deductive argument is valid because the conclusion
logically follows from its premises. It is sound due to an overwhelming amount
of evidence to substantiate the premises claims. However, it is not the place
to justify and explain this argument here, for more information please read the
chapterThe Challenge in the Qur’an from the book “The History of the
Magnificent Qur’an” published by Exhibition Islam.[10]
The point that needs to be understood here is that the
Qur’an can be shown to be Divine revelation, and therefore its claims to
knowledge are certain and factual.
Conclusion
In light of the above discussion, since science does not
claim certainty or 100% truth and there are other ways to render truths about
the world and reality then the assertion of scientism is false.
It must be noted that science can reach a level of certainty
– but this is very rare – and although highly effective, it has severe
limitations. People need to understand this and limit it to its sphere. There
are many areas of knowledge that science is de-scoped, in other words, it has
no say. Therefore, people must be aware of the fanatics in this debate
masquerading as bastions of truth and beacons of light for all to follow. These
fanatics are the science fundamentalists who advocate a narrow and dogmatic
approach to science. They presume and propagate naturalism, empiricism and
scientism, all of which are incoherent and lead to philosophical absurdities.
We strongly believe that people should beware of these popularisers, and
understand what science really is – a blessing from God with limitations and
unresolved problems concerning some of its claims to truth.
Reference
[1] Bertrand Russell. Religion and Science. Oxford
University Press. 1935, p. 8.
[2] David Hume. An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding,
p. 108.
[3] Elliot Sober “Empiricism” in The Routledge Companion to
Philosophy of Science. Edited by Stathis Psillos and Martin Curd. 2010, p. 129.
[4] Ibid, p. 131.
[5] Benjamin McMyler. Testimony, Truth and Authority. Oxford
University Press. 2011. p. 3.
[6] The Epistemology of Testimony. Edited by Jennifer Lackey
and Ernest Sosa. Clarendon Press: Oxford. 2006, p. 2.
[7] C. A. J. Coady. Testimony: A Philosophical Study. Oxford
University Press. 1992, p. 82.
[8] Benjamin McMyler. Testimony, Truth and Authority. Oxford
University Press. 2011. p 10.
[9] Keith Lehrer cited in The Epistemology of Testimony.
Oxford University Press. 2006, p. 158
[10] To purchase the book please access the following link http://www.exhibitionislam.com/books.aspx?ID=28
No comments:
Post a Comment